1 Central Simple Algebras
1.1 Basic Theory
In this chapter we define central simple algebras. We used some results in section 3.1.
A ring \(R\) is simple if the only two-sided-ideals of \(R\) are \({0}\) and \(R\). An algebra is simple if it is simple as a ring.
Division rings are simple.
Let \(A\) be a simple ring, then centre of \(A\) is a field.
Let \(0\ne x\) be an element of centre of \(A\). Then \(I := \{ xy | y\in A\} \) is a two-sided-ideal of \(A\). Since \(0\ne x\in I\), we have that \(I = A\). Therefore \(1 \in I\), hence \(x\) is invertible.
Let \(R\) be a ring and \(A\) an \(R\)-algebra, we say \(A\) is central if and only if the centre of \(A\) is \(R\)
Every commutative ring is a central algebra over itself.
Simpleness is invariant under ring isomorphism and centrality is invariant under algebra isomorphism.
If \(A\) is a central \(R\)-algerba, \(A^{\mathsf{opp}}\) is also central. .
\(R\) is a simple ring if and only if any ring homomorphism \(f : R \to S\) either injective or \(S\) is the trivial ring.
If \(R\) is simple, then the \(\ker f\) is either \(\{ 0\} \) or \(R\). The former case implies that \(f\) is injective while the latter case implies that \(S\) is the trivial ring. Conversely, let \(I\subseteq R\) be a two-sided-ideal. Consider \(\pi : R \to {}^{R}/_{I}\), either \(\pi \) is injective implying that \(I = \{ 0\} \) or that \({}^{R}/_{I}\) is the trivial ring implying that \(I = R\).
If \(A\) is a simple \(R\)-algebra, “ring homomorphism” in lemma 1.1.6 can be replaced with \(R\)-algebra homomorphism.
Assume \(R\) is a field. Let \(A, B\) be finite dimensional \(R\)-algebras where \(A\) is simple as well. Then any \(R\)-algebra homomorphism \(f:A\to B\) is bijective if \(\dim _{R}A=\dim _{R}B\).
By lemma 1.1.6, \(f\)is injective. Then \(\dim _{K}\operatorname{im}f = \dim _{K} B - \dim _{K}\ker f = \dim _{K}B\) meaning that \(f\) is surjective.
Let \(K\) be a field and \(A, B\) be \(K\)-algebras.
If \(A\) and \(B\) are central \(K\)-algebras, \(A\otimes _{K}B\) is a central \(K\)-algebra as well.
Assume \(A\) and \(B\) are central algebras, then by corollary 3.1.7 \(Z\left(A\otimes _{R}B\right)=Z\left(A\right)\otimes _{R}Z\left(B\right)=R\otimes _{R}R=R\).
If \(A\) is a simple \(K\)-algebra and \(B\) is a central simple \(K\)-algebra, \(A\otimes _{K}B\) is a central simple \(K\)-algebra as well.
By lemma 1.1.9, we need to prove \(A\otimes _{K}B\) is a simple ring. Denote \(f\) as the map \(A\to A\otimes _{K}B\). It is sufficient to prove that for every two-sided-ideal \(I\subseteq A\otimes _{K}B\), we have \(I = \left\langle f\left(f^{-1}\left(I\right)\right)\right\rangle \). Indeed, since \(A\) is simple \(f^{-1}\left(I\right)\) is either \(\left\{ 0\right\} \) or \(A\), if it is \(\left\{ 0\right\} \), then \(I=\left\{ 0\right\} \); if it is \(A\), then \(I\) is \(A\) as well.
We will prove that \(I \le \left\langle f\left(f^{-1}\left(I\right)\right)\right\rangle \), the other direction is straightforward. Without loss of generality assume \(I\ne \left\{ 0\right\} \). Let \(\mathcal{A}\) be an arbitrary basis of \(A\), by lemma 3.1.1, we see that every element \(x \in A\otimes _{K}B\) can be written as \(\sum _{i=0}^{n}\mathcal{A}_{i}\otimes b_{i}\) for some natrual number \(n\) and some choice of \(b_{i}\in B\) and \(\mathcal{A}_{i}\in \mathcal{A}\). Since \(I\) is not empty, we see there exists a non-zero element \(\omega \in I\) such that its expansion \(\sum _{i=0}^{n}\mathcal{A}_{i}\otimes b_{i}\) has the minimal \(n\). In particular, all \(b_{i}\) are non-zero and \(n\ne 0\). We have \(\omega =\mathcal{A}_{0}\otimes b_{0}+\sum _{i=1}^{n}\mathcal{A}_{i}\otimes b_{i}\). Since \(B\) is simple, \(1 \in B = \left\langle \langle b_{0} \right\rangle \); hence we write \(1\in \sum _{j=0}^{m}x_{i}b_{0}y_{i}\) for some \(x_{i},y_{i}\in B\). Define \(\Omega := \sum _{j=0}^{m}(1\otimes x_{i})\omega (1\otimes y_{i})\) which is also in \(I\). We write
For every \(\beta \in B\), we have that \(\left(1\otimes \beta \right)\Omega - \Omega \left(1\otimes \beta \right)\) is in I and is equal to
which is an expansion of \(n-1\) terms, thus \(\left(1\otimes \beta \right)\Omega -\Omega \left(1\otimes \beta \right)\) must be \(0\). Hence we conclude that for all \(i=1,\dots ,n\), \(\sum _{j=0}^{m}x_{j}b_{i}y_{j}\in Z\left(B\right)=K\). Hence for all \(i=1,\dots ,n\), we find a \(\kappa _{i}\in K\) such that \(\kappa _{i}=\sum _{j=0}^{m}x_{j}b_{i}y_{j}\). Hence we can calculate \(\Omega \) as
From this, we note that \(\mathcal{A}_{0}+\sum _{i}^{n}\kappa _{i}\cdot \mathcal{A}_{i}\in f^{-1}\left(I\right)\); since \(A\) is simple, we immediately conclude that \(f^{-1}\left(I\right) = A\), once we know \(\mathcal{A}_{0}+\sum _{i=1}^{n}\kappa _{i}\cdot \mathcal{A}_{i}\) is not zero. If it is zero, by the fact that \(\mathcal{A}\) is a linearly independent set, we conclude that \(1,\kappa _{1},\dots ,\kappa _{n}\) are all zero; which is a contradiction. Since \(f^{-1}\left(I\right) = A\), we know \(\left\langle f\left(f^{-1}I\right)\right\rangle = A \otimes _{K} B\).
Central simple algebras are stable under base change. That is, if \(L/K\) is a field extension and \(D\) is a central simple algebra over \(K\), then \(L\otimes _{K} D\) is central simple over \(L\).
By theorem 1.1.10, \(L\otimes _{K} D\) is simple. Let \(x\in Z\left(L\otimes _{K}D\right)\), by corollary 3.1.7, we have \(x\in Z\left(L\right)\otimes Z\left(D\right)=Z\left(L\right)\). Without loss of generality, we can assume that \(x = l \otimes d\) is a pure tensor, then \(l \in Z\left(L\right)\) and \(d \in K\). Therefore \(x = d\cdot l \in L\).
If \(A\otimes _{K} B\) is a simple ring, then \(A\) and \(B\) are both simple.
By symmetry, we only prove that \(A\) is simple. If \(A\) or \(B\) is the trivial ring then \(A\otimes _{K} B\) is the trivial ring, a contradiction. Thus we assume both \(A\) and \(B\) are non-trivial. Suppose \(A\) is not simple, by lemma 1.1.6, there exists a non-trivial \(K\)-algebra \(A'\) and a \(K\)-algebra homomorphism \(f : A \to A'\) such that \(\ker f \not= \{ 0\} \). Let \(F : A \otimes _{K} B\to A'\otimes _{K} B\) be the base change of \(f\), then since \(A\otimes _{K} B\) is simple and \(A'\otimes B\) is non-trivial (\(A'\) is non-trivial and \(B\) is faithfully flat because \(B\) is free), we conclude that \(F\) is injective. Then we have that
is exact. Since \(B\) is faithfully flat as a \(K\)-module, tensorig with \(B\) reflects exact sequences, therefore
is exact as well. This is contradiction since \(f\) is not injective.
1.2 Subfields of Central Simple Algebras
For any field \(K\) and \(K\)-algebra \(A\), a subfield \(B \subseteq A\) is a commutative \(K\)-subalgebra of \(A\) that is closed under inverse for any non-zero member.
Subfields inherit a natural ordering from subalgebras.
Let \(K\) be any field and \(D\) a finite dimensional central division \(K\)-algebra and \(A\) a finite dimensional central simple algebra of \(A\).
Let \(k\) be a maximal subfield of \(D\),
By lemma 3.4.11, we have that \(\dim _{K} D = \dim _{K}C_{D}(k)\cdot \dim _{K}k\). Hence it is sufficient to show that \(C_{D}(k) = k\). By the commutativity of \(k\), we have that \(k \le C_{D}(k)\). Suppose \(k \ne C_{D}(k)\): let \(a \in C_{D}(k)\) that is not in \(k\). We see that \(L := k(a)\) is another subalgebra of \(D\) that is strictly larger than \(k\); a contradiction. Therefore \(k = C_{D}(k)\) and the theorem is proved.
Suppose \(L\) is a subfield of \(A\), the following are equivalent:
\(L\) = \(C_{A}(L)\)
\(\dim _{K}A = {\left(\dim _{K}L\right)}^{2}\)
for any commutative \(K\)-subalgebra \(L' \subseteq A\), \(L \subseteq L'\) implies \(L = L'\)
We prove the following:
“1. implies 2.”: this is lemma 3.4.11.
“2. implies 1.”: Since \(L\) is commutative, we always have \(L \subseteq C_{A}(L)\). Hence we only need to show \(\dim _{K}L = \dim _{K}C_{A}(L)\). This is because by lemma 3.4.11, we have that \(\dim _{K}A = \dim _{K}L\cdot \dim _{K}C_{A}(L)\) and by 2. we have \(\dim _{K}L\cdot \dim _{K}C_{A}(L)= \dim _{K}L\cdot \dim _{K}L\).
“2. implies 3.”: Since 2. implies 1., we assume \(L = C_{A}(L)\), therefore all we need is to prove \(L' \subseteq C_{A}(L)\). Let \(x \in L'\) and \(y \in L \subseteq L'\), we need to show \(xy = yx\) which is commutativity of \(L'\).
“3. implies 1.”: By commutativity of \(L\), we always have \(L \subseteq C_{A}(L)\). For the other direction, suppose \(C_{A}(L)\not\subseteq L\), then there exists some \(a \in C_{A}(L)\) but not in \(L\). Consider \(L' = L(a)\), by 3., we have \(L' = L\) which is a contradiction.